C.S. Lewis on cover of TIME Magazine
The Chronicles of C. S. Lewis Lead to Poets’ Corner, New York Times
C. S. Lewis Superstar
C. S. Lewis: Why He Matters Today
The Chronicles of C. S. Lewis Lead to Poets’ Corner, New York Times
C. S. Lewis Superstar
C. S. Lewis: Why He Matters Today
Synopsis:
This hugely popular international bestseller is being repackaged and
rebranded as the leading title in the C.S. Lewis Signature Classics
range. One of the most popular and beloved introductions to the concept
of faith ever written, Mere Christianity has sold millions of copies
worldwide. The timeless questions of spirituality which Lewis raises
will have resonance with a new generation of readers. Mere Christianity
brings together Lewis's legendary broadcast talks of the war years,
talks in which he set out simply to 'explain and defend the belief that
has been common to nearly all Christians at all times.' Rejecting the
boundaries that divide Christianity's many denominations, C.S. Lewis
provides an unequaled opportunity for believers and nonbelievers alike
to hear a powerful, rational case for the Christian faith. This
scintillating collection confirms C.S. Lewis's reputation as one of the
leading writers and thinkers of our age.
BOOK I: RIGHT AND WRONG AS A CLUE TO MEANING OF UNIVERSE
Chapter 2: SOME OBJECTIONS
You might
think love of humanity in general was safe, but it is not. If you leave out
justice you will find yourself breaking agreements and faking evidence in
trials 'for the sake of humanity,' and become in the end a cruel and
treacherous man.
Other people wrote to me saying, 'Isn't what you
call the Moral Law just a social convention, something that is put into us by
education?' I think there is a misunderstanding here. The people who ask that
question are usually taking it for granted that if we have learned a thing from
parents and teachers, then that thing must be merely a human invention. But, of
course, that is not so. We all learned the multiplication table at school. A
child who grew up alone on a desert island would not know it. But surely it
does not follow that the multiplication table is simply a human convention,
something human beings have made up for themselves and might have made
different if they had liked? I fully agree that we learn the Rule of Decent
Behaviour from parents and teachers, and friends and books, as we learn
everything else. But some of the things we learn are mere conventions which
might have been different�Cwe learn to keep to the left of the road, but it
might just as well have been the rule to keep to the right�Cand
others of them, like mathematics, are real truths. The question is to which
class the Law of Human Nature belongs.
There are two reasons for saying it belongs to the same class as mathematics.
The first is, as I said in the first chapter, that though there are differences
between the moral ideas of one time or country and those of another, the
differences are not really very great�Cnot
nearly so great as most people imagine�Cand
you can recognise the same law running through them all: whereas mere
conventions, like the rule of the road or the kind of clothes people wear, may
differ to any extent. The other reason is this. When you think about these
differences between the morality of one people and another, do you think that
the morality of one people is ever better or worse than that of another? Have
any of the changes been improvements? If not, then of course there could never
be any moral progress. Progress means not just changing, but changing for the
better. If no set of moral ideas were truer or better than any other, there
would be no sense in preferring civilised morality to savage morality, or
Christian morality to Nazi morality. In fact, of course, we all do believe that
some moralities are better than others. We do believe that some of the people
who tried to change the moral ideas of their own age were what we would call
Reformers or Pioneers�Cpeople who understood morality better than their
neighbours did. Very well then. The moment you say that one set of moral ideas
can be better than another, you are, in fact, measuring them both by a
standard, saying that one of them conforms to that standard more nearly than
the other. But the standard that measures two things is something different from
either. You are, in fact, comparing them both with some Real Morality,
admitting that there is such a thing as a real Right, independent of what
people think, and that some people's ideas get nearer to that real Right than
others. Or put it this way. If your moral ideas can be truer, and those of the
Nazis less true, there must be something-some Real Morality�Cfor
them to be true about. The reason why your idea of New York can be truer or
less true than mine is that New York is a real place, existing quite apart from
what either of us thinks. If when each of us said 'New York' each means merely
'The town I am imagining in my own head,' how could one of us have truer ideas
than the other? There would be no question of truth or falsehood at all. In the
same way, if the Rule of Decent Behaviour meant simply 'whatever each nation
happens to approve,' there would be no sense in saying that any one nation had
ever been more correct in its approval than any other; no sense in saying that
the world could ever grow morally better or morally worse.I conclude then, that though the differences between people's ideas of Decent Behaviour often make you suspect that there is no real natural Law of Behaviour at all, yet the things we are bound to think about these differences really prove just the opposite. But one word before I end. I have met people who exaggerate the differences, because they have not distinguished between differences of morality and differences of belief about facts. For example, one man said to me, 'Three hundred years ago people in England were putting witches to death. Was that what you call the Rule of Human Nature or Right Conduct?' But surely the reason we do not execute witches is that we do not believe there are such things. If we did�Cif we really thought that there were people going about who had sold themselves to the devil and received supernatural powers from him in return and were using these powers to kill their neighbours or drive them mad or bring bad weather�Csurely we would all agree that if anyone deserved the death penalty, then these filthy quislings did? There is no difference of moral principle here: the difference is simply about matter of fact. It may be a great advance in knowledge not to believe in witches: there is no moral advance in not executing them when you do not think they are there. You would not call a man humane for ceasing to set mousetraps if he did so because he believed there were no mice in the house.
Chapter 3: THE REALITY OF THE LAW
I now go back to-what I said at the end of the first chapter, that there were two odd things about the human race. First, that they were haunted by the idea of a sort of behaviour they ought to practise, what you might call fair play, or decency, or morality, or the Law of Nature. Second, that they did not in fact do so. Now some of you may wonder why I called this odd. It may seem to you the most natural thing in the world. In particular, you may have thought I was rather hard on the human race. After all, you may say, what I call breaking the Law of Right and Wrong or of Nature, only means that people are not perfect. And why on earth should I expect them to be? That would be a good answer if what I was trying to do was to fix the exact amount of blame which is due to us for not behaving as we expect others to behave. But that is not my job at all. I am not concerned at present with blame; I am trying to find out truth. And from that point of view the very idea of something being imperfect, of its not being what it ought to be, has certain consequences.
If you take a thing like a stone or a tree, it is what it is and there seems no sense in saying it ought to have been otherwise. Of course you may say a stone is 'the wrong shape' if you want to use it for a rockery, or that a tree is a bad tree because it does not give you as much shade as you expected. But all you mean is that the stone or the tree does not happen to be convenient for some purpose of your own. You are not, except as a joke, blaming them for that. You really know, that, given the weather and the soil, the tree could not have been any different. What we, from our point of view, call a 'bad' tree is obeying the laws of its nature just as much as a 'good' one.
I now go back to-what I said at the end of the first chapter, that there were two odd things about the human race. First, that they were haunted by the idea of a sort of behaviour they ought to practise, what you might call fair play, or decency, or morality, or the Law of Nature. Second, that they did not in fact do so. Now some of you may wonder why I called this odd. It may seem to you the most natural thing in the world. In particular, you may have thought I was rather hard on the human race. After all, you may say, what I call breaking the Law of Right and Wrong or of Nature, only means that people are not perfect. And why on earth should I expect them to be? That would be a good answer if what I was trying to do was to fix the exact amount of blame which is due to us for not behaving as we expect others to behave. But that is not my job at all. I am not concerned at present with blame; I am trying to find out truth. And from that point of view the very idea of something being imperfect, of its not being what it ought to be, has certain consequences.
If you take a thing like a stone or a tree, it is what it is and there seems no sense in saying it ought to have been otherwise. Of course you may say a stone is 'the wrong shape' if you want to use it for a rockery, or that a tree is a bad tree because it does not give you as much shade as you expected. But all you mean is that the stone or the tree does not happen to be convenient for some purpose of your own. You are not, except as a joke, blaming them for that. You really know, that, given the weather and the soil, the tree could not have been any different. What we, from our point of view, call a 'bad' tree is obeying the laws of its nature just as much as a 'good' one.
No comments:
Post a Comment